A Brief History of Space (1/4)

This post is based on a chapter of my book  “The Wraparound Universe” but is much more illustrated.  The chapter is divided into 4 parts, here is the first one.

*************

That which keeps quiet beyond everything, is this in fact simply what I name Space? . . . Space! An idea! A word! A breath!
Jean Tardieu

There is no space or time given a priori; to each moment in human history, to each degree of perfection of our physical theories of the Universe, there corresponds a conception of those fundamental categories of thought known as space, time, and matter. To each new conception, our mental image of the Universe must adapt itself, and we must accept that “common sense” was found lacking. For example, if space is limited by a boundary, what is there beyond it? Nothing? It is difficult to imagine that, by voyaging sufficiently far in a given direction, one could reach a point beyond which nothing more exists, not even space. It is just as troubling to think of an infinitely large Universe. What would be the meaning of any measurable, that is to say finite, thing with respect to the infinite?

A possible representation of Anaximander learning Pythagoras on his left, detail of Raphael's famous painting The School of Athens.
A possible representation of Anaximander learning Pythagoras on his left, detail of Raphael’s famous painting The School of Athens.

These types of questions were formulated in the sixth century BCE, in ancient Greece, where they rapidly became the object of controversy. The first schools of scholars and philosophers, called “presocratic” (although they were spread over two centuries and were quite different from each other), each attempted in their way to rationally explain the “world,” meaning the ensemble formed by the Earth and the stars, conceived as an organized system. For Anaximander, from the school of Miletus, the world where observable phenomena take place was necessarily finite. Nevertheless, it was plunged within a surrounding medium, the apeiron, corresponding to what we today consider as space. This term signifies both infinite (unlimited, eternal) and indefinite (undetermined). For his contemporary, Thales, the universal medium was made of water, and the world was a hemispheric bubble floating in the middle of this infinite liquid mass.

We meet up again with this intuitive conception of a finite material world bathing in an infinite receptacle space with other thinkers: Heraclitus, Empedocles, and especially the Stoics, who added the idea of a world in pulsation, passing through periodic phases of explosions and deflagrations.

Atomism, founded in the fifth century by Leucippus and Democritus, advocated a completely different version of cosmic infinity. It maintained that the Universe was constructed from two primordial elements: atoms and the void. Indivisible and elementary, (atomos means “that which cannot be divided”), atoms exist for all eternity, only differing in their size and shape. They are infinite in number. All bodies result from the coalescence of atoms in motion; the number of combinations being infinite, it follows that the celestial bodies are themselves infinite in number: this is the thesis of the plurality of worlds. The formation of these worlds is produced within a receptacle without bounds: the void (kenon). This “space” has no other property than being infinite and accordingly matter has no influence on it: it is absolute, given a priori.

Part of a fresco in the portico of the National University of Athens representing Anaxagoras.
Part of a fresco in the portico of the National University of Athens representing Anaxagoras.

The atomist philosophy was strongly criticized by Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle. Moreover, by affirming that the universe is not governed by gods, but by elementary matter and the void, it inevitably entered into conflict with the religious authorities. In the fourth century BCE, Anaxagoras of Clazomenae was the first scholar in history to be accused of impiety; however, defended by powerful friends, he was acquitted and was able to flee far from the hostility of Athens. Thanks to its two most illustrious spokesmen, Epicurus (341-270 BCE), who founded the first school that allowed female students and Lucretius (first century BCE), author of a magnificent cosmological poem, On the Nature of Things, atomism continued to flourish until the advent of Christianity. It was however marginalized over the course of the first centuries of the christian era, and would not again be part of mainstream science until the seventeenth century.

The cosmos according to Epicurus' atomist system.
The cosmos according to Epicurus’ atomist system.
An English edition of Lucretius' De Rerum Natura, published in Oxford.
An English edition of Lucretius’ De Rerum Natura, published in Oxford.

Plato (428-347 BCE) considered a finite universe, enclosed by an ultimate sphere that contained the stars. To speak of “space” (the English term comes from the Latin spatium), Greek terminology used different names: khaos, kosmos, apeiron, kenon, pan (“all”), ouranos (“sky”), etc. In Timaeus, a specific term was introduced, khora, which designates the expanse or space as a receptacle for matter, and defined by it. Plato went on to play an essential role in the evolution of astronomical thought by insisting upon the fact that scientists must not content themselves with contemplation of the stars but must also use mathematics and geometry to discover the true nature of the celestial bodies and explain their movements. All of Greek astronomy, from Aristotle and Eudoxus to Ptolemy (who would create the crowning form of these ideas five centuries later), would flower around this precept of a geometric astronomy.

The famous central part of Raphael's School of Athens, representing Plato and his former pupil Aristotle.
The famous central part of Raphael’s School of Athens, representing Plato and his former pupil Aristotle.

Aristotle (384-322 BCE) opposed himself to Plato by not developing a theory of space properly speaking, but a theory of place (topos), distinct from the expanse and independent of matter. The place is the limit which surrounds things. The universe is not a place, but the place, the sum total of all the places occupied by bodies. Opposing himself also to the atomists, Aristotle believed that the number of bodies was necessarily finite. On the cosmological level, his conception approached that of Plato: a fixed Earth at the center of a finite world, circumscribed by the sphere which contains all the bodies of the universe. But this exterior sphere is “nowhere,” since beyond it there is nothing, neither void nor expanse.

There also exists, in Greek antiquity, three great schools of cosmological thought. One, which includes the Milesians, Stoics, etc., makes a distinction between the physical world (the material universe) and space: the universe is considered as a finite island plunged within an infinite extracosmic space without any properties, which surrounds and contains it. The two others, atomist and aristotelian, consider that the very existence of space follows from the existence of bodies; the physical world and space coincide; they are infinite for the atomists, finite for the aristotelians. Even today, most people have in mind one or the other of these conceptions.

The defenders of a finite universe nevertheless come across a logical difficulty: if what is beyond the world still makes up part of the world, the world cannot be bounded without there being a contradiction. This “edge paradox” would not be resolved until the end of the nineteenth century.

A pictorial representation of the cosmos according to Stoic philosophy.
A pictorial representation of the cosmos according to Stoic philosophy.

In the same way that atomism was judged to be too materialist, the Aristotelian doctrine, which implies eternal time and a non-created universe, was rejected by the first theologians of christianity. Until the sixth century, the cosmological models of the West returned to the archaic conceptions of the Milesians, namely a finite cosmos bathing in the void, with the added distinction that the cosmos takes the form of a tabernacle, or of a heart.

A sketch of VIth centrury Cosmas’ pattern of the universe (Codex Sinaiticus graecus 1186, 11th century, St. Katherine's monastery, Sinai).
A sketch of VIth centrury Cosmas’ pattern of the universe (Codex Sinaiticus graecus 1186, 11th century, St. Katherine’s monastery, Sinai).

The world according to the German mystic Hildegarde von Bingen, 11th century.
The world according to the German mystic Hildegarde von Bingen, 12th century.

*********

Second part to come

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *